• 検索結果がありません。

Lec8 最近の更新履歴 yyasuda's website

N/A
N/A
Protected

Academic year: 2017

シェア "Lec8 最近の更新履歴 yyasuda's website"

Copied!
16
0
0

読み込み中.... (全文を見る)

全文

(1)

Lecture 8: Preference, Choice, and Utility

Advanced Microeconomics I

Yosuke YASUDA

National Graduate Institute for Policy Studies

November 5, 2013

(2)

Preferences

To construct a model of individual choice, the notion of

preferences plays a central role in economic theory, which specifies the form of consistency or inconsistency in the person’s choices. We view preferences as the mental attitude of an individual toward alternatives independent of any actual choice.

We require only that the individual make binary comparisons, that is, that she only examine two choice alternatives at a time and make a decision regarding those two.

For each pair of alternatives in the choice set X, the description of preferences should provide an answer to the question of how the agent compares the two alternatives.

We present two versions of question: questionnaires P and R. For each version we formulate the consistency requirements necessary to make the responses “preferences” and examine the connection between the two formulations.

(3)

Questionnaire P

P(x, y) for all distinct x and y in the set X:

Q How do you compare x and y? Tick one and only one of the following three options:

1. I prefer x to y (or, x is strictly preferred to y): x ≻ y 2. I prefer y to x (or, y is strictly preferred to x): y ≻ x 3. I am indifferent (or, x is indifferent to y): x ∼ y

Note that we implicitly assume that the elements in X are all comparable, and ignore the intensity of preferences.

A legal answer to the questionnaire P can be formulated as a function f which assigns to any pair (x, y) of distinct elements in X exactly one of the three values: x ≻ y, y ≻ x or x ∼ y. That is,

f(x, y) =

 x≻ y y≻ x x∼ y

.

(4)

Preference P (1)

Preferences are characterized by axioms that are intended to give formal mathematical expression to fundamental aspects of choice behavior and attitudes toward the objects of choice.

The following basic axioms are (almost) always imposed.

Def Preferences (P ) on a set X are a function f that assigns to any pair (x, y) of distinct elements in X exactly one of the three values: x ≻ y, y ≻ x or x ∼ y so that for any three different elements x, y and z in X, the following two properties hold:

1. No order effect: f (x, y) = f (y, x). 2. Transitivity:

2.1 if f (x, y) = x ≻ y and f (y, z) = y ≻ z, then f (x, z) = x ≻ z, and

2.2 if f (x, y) = x ∼ y and f (y, z) = y ∼ z, then f (x, z) = x ∼ z.

(5)

Preference P (2)

The first property requires the answer to P (x, y) being identical to the answer to P (y, x), and the second requires that the answer to P(x, y) and P (y, z) are consistent with the answer to P (x, z) in a particular way.

Ex Non-preference relation

For any x, y ∈R, f(x, y)(= f(y, x)) = x ≻ y if x ≥ y + 1 and f(x, y) = x ∼ y if |x − y| < 1. This is not a preference relation since transitivity is violated. For instance, suppose

x= 1, y = 1.8, z = 2.6. Then,

f(x, y) = x ∼ y and f (y, z) = y ∼ z, but f (x, z) = z ≻ x, which violates transitivity (2-2).

(6)

Questionnaire R

R(x, y) for all x, y ∈ X, not necessarily distinct:

Q Is x at least as preferred as y? Tick one and only one of the following two options:

1. Yes (or, x is at least as good as y): x % y. 2. No (or, x is strictly worse than y): x y.

Def Preferences (R) on a set X is a binary relation % on X satisfying the following two axioms.

Completeness (Axiom 1):

For any x, y ∈ X, x % y or y % x. Transitivity (Axiom 2):

For any x, y, z ∈ X, if x % y and y % z, then x % z.

(7)

Remarks on the Axioms

Completeness formalizes the notion that the individual can make comparisons, that is, that she has the ability to discriminate and the necessary knowledge to evaluate alternatives. It says the individual can examine any two distinct alternatives.

Transitivity gives a very particular form to the requirement that the individual choices be consistent. Although we require only that she be capable of comparing two alternatives at a time, the axiom of transitivity requires that those pairwise comparisons be linked together in a consistent way.

Rm The money pump argument when transitivity is violated. (see, for example, Rubinstein, lecture 3)

(8)

Equivalence of the Two Preferences

We can translate one formulation of preferences to another by the following mapping (bijection). Note that completeness guarantees

“x y and y  x” never happen.

f(x, y) = x ≻ y ⇔ x % y and y  x.

f(x, y) = y ≻ x ⇔ y % x and x y.

f(x, y) = x ∼ y ⇔ x % y and y % x.

In our lectures, we take the second definition, i.e., preference (R), and denote x ≻ y when both x % y and y x, and x ∼ y, when x% y and y % x.

Def A preference (R) is called a preference relation.

(9)

Utility Representation

Rev Function U : X → R represents the preference % if for all x and y ∈ X, x % y if and only if U (x) ≥ U (y). If the function U represents the preference relation %, we refer to it as a utility function and we say that % has a utility representation.

Q Under what conditions do utility representations exist?

Thm If % is a preference relation on a finite set X, then % has a utility representation with values being natural numbers.

Proof There is a minimal (resp. maximal) element (an element a∈ X is minimal (resp. maximal) if a - x (resp. a % x) for any x∈ X) in any finite set A ⊂ X. We can construct a sequence of sets from the minimal to the maximal and can assign natural numbers according to their ordering.

(10)

Continuous Preferences

To guarantee the existence of a utility representation over consumption set, i.e., an infinite subset ofRn, we need some additional axiom.

Def A preference relation % on X is continuous (Axiom 3) if {xn} (a sequence of consumption bundles) with limit x satisfies the following two conditions for all y ∈ X.

1. if x ≻ y, then for all n sufficiently large, xn≻ y, and 2. if y ≻ x, then for all n sufficiently large, y ≻ xn.

The equivalent definition of continuity is that the “at least as good as” and “no better than” sets for each point x ∈ X are closed. This axiom rules out certain discontinuous behavior and guarantees that sudden preference reversals do not occur.

Fg Figures 1.2 and 1.3 (see JR, pp.9)

(11)

Continuous Utility

Given axioms 1-3, we can establish the existence of the (continuous) utility function.

Thm Assume that X is a convex subset ofRn. If % is a continuous preference relation on X, then % is represented by a continuous utility function.

Here are two remarks on continuity.

1. If % on X is represented by a continuous function U , then % must be continuous.

2. The lexicographic preferences are not continuous.

Thm The lexicographic preference relation %L on

[0, 1] × [0, 1], i.e., (a1, a2) %L(b1, b2) if a1> b1 or both a1 = b1

and a2 ≥ b2, does not have a utility representation.

(12)

Existence of Solutions to Consumer Problems

Thm If % is a continuous preference relation, then all consumer problems have a solution.

Proof Since the budget set is convex, we can apply the first theorem in the previous slide to establish that the preferences are represented by a continuous utility function.

Then, by the Weielstrass theorem, there exists a maximum (and minimum) value of continuous functions if the domain is a compact (that is, closed and bounded) set and a range isR. Since every budget set is compact and a utility function is continuous, there must exist a consumption bundle which gives a maximum utility value, a solution of the consumer problem.

(13)

Revealed Preferences

Important difference between choice (demand) and preferences or utility is that the former is observable while the latter cannot be. We may want to develop the theory which is based on the observable choice behaviors, not on preferences or utility.

We say that the preferences % (fully) rationalize the demand function x if for any (p, ω) the bundle x(p, ω) is the unique

%best bundle within B(p, ω).

We say that a is revealed to be better than b, if there is (p, ω) so that both a and b are in B(p, ω) and a = x(p, ω).

Q What are general conditions guaranteeing that a demand function x(p, ω) can be rationalized?

→ Present two axioms of revealed preferences.

(14)

Weak Axiom of Revealed Preferences

Def (Weak Axiom) The weak axiom of revealed preferences (WA) is a property of choice function which says that it is

impossible that a be revealed to be better than b and b be revealed to be better than a. That is,

if px(p, ω) ≤ ω and x(p, ω) 6= x(p, ω), then px(p, ω) > ω.

Fg Figure 2.3 (see JR, pp.92)

Rm Note that any choice function rationalized by some preference relation must satisfy WA.

(15)

Weak Axiom ⇒ Law of Demand

Thm Let x(p, ω) be a choice function satisfying Walras’s Law and WA. Then,

1. x(·) is homogeneous of degree zero, and

2. if ω = px(p, ω), then either x(p, ω) = x(p, ω) or (p− p)(x(p, ω) − x(p, ω)) < 0.

Proof The proof for 1 is left for the assignment. Assume that x(p, ω) 6= x(p, ω). By Walras’s Law and the assumption that ω = px(p, ω):

(p− p)(x(p, ω) − x(p, ω))

= px(p, ω) − px(p, ω) − px(p, ω) + px(p, ω)

= ω− ω− px(p, ω) + ω

= ω − px(p, ω).

(16)

Strong Axiom of Revealed Preferences

The previous theorem implies that the compensated (Hicksian) demand function y(p) = x(p, px(p, ω)) satisfies the law of demand, that is, yk is decreasing in pk.

WA is not a sufficient condition for extending the binary relation % (defined from the choice function) into a complete and transitive relation. The following stronger condition than WA is known to be necessary and sufficient.

Def (Strong Axiom) Choice function satisfies the strong axiom of revealed preferences (SA) if for every sequence of distinct bundles x0, x1, ..., xk, where x0 is revealed preferred to x1, and x1 is revealed preferred to x2, ..., and xk−1 is revealed preferred to xk, it is not the case that xk is revealed preferred to x0.

参照

関連したドキュメント

She reviews the status of a number of interrelated problems on diameters of graphs, including: (i) degree/diameter problem, (ii) order/degree problem, (iii) given n, D, D 0 ,

We remark that there is a related well-known problem: do there exist compact anti-self-dual Einstein manifolds with negative scalar curvature, besides hyperbolic and

On the other hand, from physical arguments, it is expected that asymptotically in time the concentration approach certain values of the minimizers of the function f appearing in

In [9] a free energy encoding marked length spectra of closed geodesics was introduced, thus our objective is to analyze facts of the free energy of herein comparing with the

classes of harmonic functions are introduced and mixed Zaremba’s bound- ary value problem is studed in them, i.e., the problem of constructing a harmonic function when on a part of

σ(L, O) is a continuous function on the space of compact convex bodies with specified interior point, and it is also invariant under affine transformations.. The set R of regular

In this section we state our main theorems concerning the existence of a unique local solution to (SDP) and the continuous dependence on the initial data... τ is the initial time of

A Darboux type problem for a model hyperbolic equation of the third order with multiple characteristics is considered in the case of two independent variables.. In the class