• 検索結果がありません。

Lec1 最近の更新履歴 yyasuda's website

N/A
N/A
Protected

Academic year: 2017

シェア "Lec1 最近の更新履歴 yyasuda's website"

Copied!
15
0
0

読み込み中.... (全文を見る)

全文

(1)

Lecture 1: Expected Utility

Advanced Microeconomics II

Yosuke YASUDA

National Graduate Institute for Policy Studies

December 3, 2013

(2)

Decision under Uncertainty

We have so far not distinguished between individual’s actions and consequences, but many choices made by agents take place under conditions of uncertainty.

This lecture discusses such a decision under uncertainty, i.e., an environment in which the correspondence between actions and consequences is not deterministic but stochastic.

To discuss a decision under uncertainty, we extend the domain of choice functions. The choice of an action is viewed as choosing a “lottery” where the prizes are the consequences.

An implicit assumption is that the decision maker does not care about the nature of the random factors but only about the distribution of consequences.

(3)

Lotteries (1)

We consider preferences and choices over the set of “lotteries.”

Let S be a set of consequences (prizes). We assume that S is a finite set and the number of its elements (= |S|) is S.

A lottery p is a function that assigns a nonnegative number to each prize s, where Ps∈Sp(s) = 1 (here p(s) is the objective probability of obtaining the prize s given the lottery p).

Let α ◦ x ⊕ (1 − α) ◦ y denote the lottery in which the prize x is realized with probability α and the prize y with 1 − α.

Denote by L(S) the (infinite) space containing all lotteries with prizes in S. That is, {x ∈ RS+|Pxs= 1}.

We will discuss preferences over L(S).

(4)

Lotteries (2)

We impose the following three assumptions on the lotteries. 1. 1 ◦ x ⊕ (1 − 1) ◦ y ∼ x: Getting a prize with probability one is

the same as getting the prize for certain.

2. α◦ x ⊕ (1 − α) ◦ y ∼ (1 − α) ◦ y ⊕ α ◦ x: The consumer does not care about the order in which the lottery is described. 3. β◦ (α ◦ x ⊕ (1 − α) ◦ y) ⊕ (1 − β) ◦ y ∼ (βα) ◦ x ⊕ (1 − βα) ◦ y:

A consumer’s perception of a lottery depends only on the net probabilities of receiving the various prizes.

The first two assumptions appear to be innocuous.

The third assumption sometimes called “reduction of compound lotteries” is somewhat suspect.

There is some evidence to suggest that consumers treat compound lotteries different than one-shot lotteries.

(5)

St Petersburg Paradox (1)

The most primitive way to evaluate a lottery is to calculate its mathematical expectation, i.e., E[p] =Ps∈Sp(s)s.

Daniel Bernoulli first doubt this approach in the 18th century when he examined the famous St. Pertersburg paradox.

Ex St Petersburg Paradox

A fair coin is tossed until it shows heads for the first time. If the first head appears on the k-th trial, a player wins $2k. How much are you willing to pay to participate in this lottery?

Rm The expected value of the lottery is infinite: 2

2 + 22 22 +

23

23 + · · · = 1 + 1 + 1 + · · · = ∞.

(6)

St Petersburg Paradox (2)

The St Petersburg paradox shows that maximizing your dollar expectation may not always be a good idea. It suggests that an agent in risky situation might want to maximize the expectation of some “utility function” with decreasing marginal utility:

E[u(x)] = u(2)1

2+ u(4) 1

4+ u(8) 1 8+ · · ·, which can be a finite number.

Q Under what kinds of conditions does a decision maker maximizes the expectation of some “utility function”?

Rm By utility theory, we know that for any preference relation defined on the space of lotteries that satisfies continuity, there is a utility representation U : L(S) → R, continuous in the

probabilities, such that p % q if and only if U (p) ≥ U (q).

(7)

Expected Utility Theory (1)

We will use the following two axioms to isolate a family of preference relations which have a representation by a more structured utility function.

Independence Axiom (I): For any p, q, r ∈ L(S) and any α∈ (0, 1), p % q ⇔ α ◦ p ⊕ (1 − α) ◦ r % α ◦ q ⊕ (1 − α) ◦ r.

Continuity Axiom (C): If p ≻ q ≻ r, then there exists α∈ (0, 1) such that

q∼ [α ◦ p ⊕ (1 − α) ◦ r].

Thm Let % be a preference relation over L(S) satisfying the I and C. There are numbers (v(s))s∈S such that

p% q⇔ U (p) =X

s∈S

p(s)v(s) ≥ U (q) =X

s∈S

q(s)v(s).

(8)

Expected Utility Theory (2)

Sketch of the proof Let M and m be a best and a worst certain lotteries in L(S). When M ∼ m, choosing v(s) = 0 for all s we havePs∈Sp(s)v(s) = 0 for all p ∈ L(S).

Consider the case that M ≻ m. By I and C, there must be a single number v(s) ∈ [0, 1] such that

v(s) ◦ M ⊕ (1 − v(s)) ◦ m ∼ [s]

where [s] is a certain lottery with prize s, i.e., [s] = 1 ◦ s. In particular, v(M ) = 1 and v(m) = 0. I implies that

p∼ (X

s∈S

p(s)v(s)) ◦ M ⊕ (1 −X

s∈S

p(s)v(s)) ◦ m. Since M ≻ m, we can show that

p% q⇔X

s∈S

p(s)v(s) ≥X

s∈S

q(s)v(s).

(9)

vNM Utility Function (1)

Note the function U is a utility function representing the preferences on L(S) while v is a utility function defined over S, which is the building block for the construction of U (p). We refer to v as a vNM (Von Neumann-Morgenstern) utility function.

Q How can we construct the vNM utility function?

Let si(∈ S), i = 1, ..., K be a set of consequences and s1, sK be the best and the worst consequences. That is, for any i,

[s1] % [si] % [sK].

Then, construct a function v : S → [0, 1] in the following way: v(s1) = 1 and v(sK) = 0, and

[sj] ∼ v(sj) ◦ [s1] ⊕ (1 − v(sj) ◦ [sK] for all j.

By continuity axiom, we can find a unique value of v(sj) ∈ [0, 1].

(10)

vNM Utility Function (2)

Q To what extent, vNM utility function is unique?

The vNM utilities are unique up to positive affine transformation (multiplication by a positive number and adding any scalar) and are not invariant to arbitrary monotonic transformation.

Thm Suppose % is a preference relation defined over L(S) and let v(s) be the vNM utilities representing the preference relation. Then, defining w(s) = αv(s) + β for all s (for some α > 0 and some β), the utility function W (p) =Ps∈Sp(s)w(s) also represents %.

(11)

vNM Utility Function (3)

Proof For any lotteries p, q ∈ L(S), p % q if and only if X

s∈S

p(s)v(s) ≥X

s∈S

q(s)v(s).

Now, the followings hold. X

s∈S

p(s)w(s) =X

s∈S

p(s)(αv(s) + β) = αX

s∈S

p(s)v(s) + β. X

s∈S

q(s)w(s) =X

s∈S

q(s)(αv(s) + β) = αX

s∈S

q(s)v(s) + β.

Thus,Ps∈Sp(s)v(s) ≥Ps∈Sq(s)v(s) holds if and only if P

s∈Sp(s)w(s) ≥

P

s∈Sq(s)w(s) (for α > 0).

(12)

Allais Paradox (1)

Many experiments reveal systematic deviations from vNM assumptions. The most famous one is the Allais paradox.

Ex Allais paradox Choose first the between

L1 = [3000] and L2 = 0.8 ◦ [4000] ⊕ 0.2 ◦ [0] and then choose between

L3 = 0.5 ◦ [3000] ⊕ 0.5 ◦ [0] and L4 = 0.4 ◦ [4000] ⊕ 0.6 ◦ [0]. Note that L3= 0.5 ◦ L1⊕ 0.5 ◦ [0] and L4= 0.5 ◦ L2⊕ 0.5 ◦ [0]. Axiom I requires that the preference between L1 and L2 be the same as that between L3 and L4. However, a majority of people express the preferences L1 ≻ L2 and L3 ≺ L4, violating the axiom.

(13)

Allais paradox (2)

Assume L1 ≻ L2 but α ◦ L ⊕ (1 − α) ◦ L1≺ α ◦ L ⊕ (1 − α) ◦ L2. (In our example of Allais paradox, α = 0.5 and L = [0].)

Then, we can perform the following trick on the decision maker: 1. Take α ◦ L ⊕ (1 − α) ◦ L1.

2. Take instead α ◦ L ⊕ (1 − α) ◦ L2, which you prefer (and you pay me something...).

3. Let us agree to replace L2 with L1 in case L2 realizes (and you pay me something now...).

4. Note that you hold α ◦ L ⊕ (1 − α) ◦ L1. 5. Let us start from the beginning...

This argument may make the independence axiom looks somewhat reasonable (and Allais paradox unreasonable).

(14)

Zeckhouser’s Paradox (1)

Allais paradox can be viewed as a violation of independence axiom. The following paradox also shows that many people do not

necessarily follow the expected utility maximization behavior.

Ex Zeckhauser’s paradox

Some bullets are loaded into a revolver with six chambers. The cylinder is then spun and the gun pointed at your head.

Would you be prepared to pay more to get one bullet removed when only one bullet was loaded, or when four bullets were loaded?

Q People usually say they would pay more in the first case, because they would then be buying their lives for certain. Is this decision reasonable?

Rm Note that you cannot use your money once you die...

(15)

Zeckhouser’s Paradox (2)

Suppose $X (resp. $Y ) is the most that you are willing to pay to get one bullet removed from a gun containing one (resp. four) bullet. Let L mean death, and W mean being alive after paying nothing. Let C mean being alive after paying $X, and D mean being alive after paying $Y . Note that

u(D) < u(C) ⇔ D ≺ C ⇔ X < Y . Let u(L) = 0 and u(W ) = 1. Then,

u(C) = 1

6u(L) + 5

6u(W ) = 5 6, and 1

2u(L) + 1

2u(D) = 2

3u(L) + 1

3u(W ) ⇒ u(D) = 2 3. Since u(D) < u(C), you must be ready to pay less to get one bullet removed when only one bullet was loaded than when four bullets were loaded.

参照

関連したドキュメント

The approach based on the strangeness index includes un- determined solution components but requires a number of constant rank conditions, whereas the approach based on

This Lecture is devoted to a review of the relevant mathematical concepts, such as Lie algebroid, Courant bracket, Dirac structure and generalized complex geometry (also its

Keywords Algebraic 2–complex, Wall’s D(2)–problem, geometric realiza- tion of algebraic 2–complexes, homotopy classification of 2–complexes, gen- eralized quaternion groups,

In this paper we study multidimensional fractional advection-dispersion equations in- volving fractional directional derivatives both from a deterministic and a stochastic point

The key point is the concept of a Hamiltonian system, which, contrary to the usual approach, is not re- lated with a single Lagrangian, but rather with an Euler–Lagrange form

The correspondence between components of the locus of limit linear series and Young tableaux is defined so that on the elliptic curves C i whose indices do not appear in the

In this paper we show how to obtain a result closely analogous to the McAlister theorem for a certain class of inverse semigroups with zero, based on the idea of a Brandt

An integral inequality is deduced from the negation of the geometrical condition in the bounded mountain pass theorem of Schechter, in a situation where this theorem does not