• 検索結果がありません。

Lec5 最近の更新履歴 yyasuda's website

N/A
N/A
Protected

Academic year: 2017

シェア "Lec5 最近の更新履歴 yyasuda's website"

Copied!
11
0
0

読み込み中.... (全文を見る)

全文

(1)

Lecture 5: Consumer Demand

Advanced Microeconomics I

Yosuke YASUDA

National Graduate Institute for Policy Studies

October 22, 2013

(2)

Convex Sets and Concave Functions

Def S ⊂ R n is a convex set if for all x1, x2∈ S, tx1+ (1 − t)x2 ∈ S ∀t ∈ [0, 1].

Def Let D be a convex set and x t= tx1+ (1 − t)x2. f : D → R is a concave function if for all x1, x2∈ D,

f(xt) ≥ tf (x1) + (1 − t)f (x2) ∀t ∈ [0, 1].

Fg Figures A1.5 and A1.27 (see JR, pp.502 and pp.534) The points below the graph of all concave regions appear to be convex. Formally, the next theorem holds.

Thm Let A := (x, y)|x ∈ D, f (x) ≥ y be the set of points “on and below” the graph of f : D → R, where D ⊂ Rn is a convex set. Then,

f is a concave function ⇐⇒ A is a convex set.

(3)

Convex Preference (1)

There are three equivalent definitions of convex preferences. Def The preference relation % satisfies convexity if

1. x% y and α ∈ (0, 1) implies that αx + (1 − α)y % y. 2. For all x, y and z such that z = αx + (1 − α)y for some

α∈ (0, 1), either z % x or z % y.

3. For all y, the set AsGoodAs(y) := {z ∈ X|z % y} is convex. The notion of convex preferences captures the following intuitions: 1. If x is preferred to y, then going part of the way from y to x

is also an improvement upon y.

2. If z is between x and y then it is impossible that both x and y are better than z.

3. If both x1 and x2 are better than y, then the average of x1 and x2 is definitely better than y.

(4)

Convex Preference (2)

Convexity has a stronger version.

Def The preference relation % satisfies strict convexity if a % y, b% y, a 6= b and λ ∈ (0, 1) imply that λa + (1 − λ)b ≻ y.

Q How is the convexity of preferences translated into properties of the utility function?

Def A function u(·) : X → R is quasi-concave if for all x, y ∈ X, u(αx + (1 − α)y) ≥ min[u(x), u(y)]

holds for all α ∈ (0, 1). u(·) is strictly quasi-concave if for all x6= y in X,

u(αx + (1 − α)y) > min[u(x), u(y)] holds for all α ∈ (0, 1).

(5)

Properties of Convex Preference

Convex preferences expressed by utility functions.

Thm Suppose % is represented by utility function u(·). Then, 1. u(x) is quasiconcave if and only if % is convex.

2. u(x) is strictly quasiconcave if and only if % is strictly convex. Convexity induces a simple solution structure.

Thm Convex preference satisfies the following properties. 1. If % is convex, then the set of solutions for a choice from

B(p, ω) is convex.

2. If % is strictly convex, then every consumer problem has at most one solution.

(6)

Proof

We give the proof for each property in the second theorem.

1. Assume that both x and y maximize % given B(p, ω). By the convexity of the budget set B(p, ω) we have

αx+ (1 − α)y ∈ B(p, ω) and, by the convexity of %, αx+ (1 − α)y % x % z for all α ∈ [0, 1] and z ∈ B(p, ω). Thus, αx + (1 − α)y is also a solution to the consumer problem.

2. Assume that both x and y (where x 6= y) are solutions to the consumer problem B(p, ω). By the convexity of the budget set B(p, ω) we have αx + (1 − α)y ∈ B(p, ω) and, by the strict convexity of %, αx + (1 − α)y ≻ z for all α ∈ (0, 1) and z∈ B(p, ω), which is a contradiction of x being % optimal in B(p, ω).

(7)

(Marshallian) Demand Function

Thm The demand function x(p, ω) satisfies the following: 1. Homogeneous of degree zero:

x(p, ω) = x(λp, λω) for any λ > 0.

2. Walras’s Law: If the preferences are monotonic, then any solution x to the consumer problem B(p, ω) is located on its budget line, i.e., px(p, ω) = ω.

3. Continuity: If % is a continuous preference, then the demand function is continuous in p and in ω.

Proof We give the sketch of the proof for 1 and 2.

1. The budget sets are identical, i.e, B(p, ω) = B(λp, λω). 2. If px(p, ω) < ω, there must exist some consumption bundle

x with x ≪ x and px(p, ω) ≤ ω. By monotonicity, x must be strictly preferred to x, which contradicts x being a solution of the consumer problem.

(8)

Indirect Utility Function

There are several properties that the indirect utility function possesses.

Thm If u(x) is continuous and strictly increasing on Rn+, then

v(p, ω) is

1. Continuous in p and ω.

2. Homogeneous of degree zero in (p, ω). 3. Strictly increasing in ω.

4. Decreasing in p. 5. Quasiconvex in (p, ω).

6. Roy’s identity: If v(p, ω) is differentiable at (p0, ω0), then

xi(p0, ω0) = −

∂v(p00)

∂pi

∂v(p00)

∂ω

, i = 1, ..., n.

(9)

More on Roy’s Identity

Roy’s identity says that the consumer’s Marshallian demand for good i is simply the ratio of the partial derivatives of indirect utility with respect to pi and ω after a sign change.

By the Envelope theorem and Lagrangian method,

∂v(p0, ω0)

∂pi

= −λxi(p0, ω0) and

∂v(p0, ω0)

∂ω = λ,

which implies

∂v(p00)

∂pi

∂v(p00)

∂ω

= xi(p0, ω0).

(10)

Expenditure Function

There are several properties that the expenditure function possesses.

Thm If u(x) is continuous and strictly increasing on Rn+, then

e(p, u) is

1. Continuous in p and ω.

2. Homogeneous of degree 1 in p. 3. Strictly increasing in u, for all p ≫ 0. 4. Increasing in p.

5. Concave in p.

If, u(·) is strictly quasi-concave, we have

6. Shephard’s lemma: e(p, u) is differentiable in p at (p0, u0) with p0≫ 0, and

∂e(p0, u0)

∂pi = x

hi(p0, u0), i = 1, ..., n.

(11)

More on Shephard’s Lemma

To prove Shephard’s Lemma, we appeal to the Envelope theorem. Note that EMP and expenditure function can be rewritten as:

−e(p, u) = max

x∈Rn+

−px s.t. u(x) ≥ u,

Applying the Envelope theorem to this maximization problem,

∂− e(p0, u0)

∂pi =

∂L

∂pi = −x

h

i(p0, u0).

where L is the corresponding Lagrangian function: L = −px + λ(u(x) − u).

Canceling out negative signs, we obtain the Shephard’s lemma.

参照

関連したドキュメント

Rhoudaf; Existence results for Strongly nonlinear degenerated parabolic equations via strong convergence of truncations with L 1 data..

Assuming that Ω ⊂ R n is a two-sided chord arc domain (meaning that Ω 1 and Ω 2 are NTA-domains and that ∂Ω is Ahlfors) they also prove ([KT3, Corol- lary 5.2]) that if log ˜ k

Theorem 3.5 can be applied to determine the Poincar´ e-Liapunov first integral, Reeb inverse integrating factor and Liapunov constants for the case when the polynomial

Straube; Sobolev estimates for the ∂-Neumann operator on domains in C n admitting a defining function that is plurisubharmonic on the boundary, Math.. Charpentier; Boundary values

In this paper, we study the existence and nonexistence of positive solutions of an elliptic system involving critical Sobolev exponent perturbed by a weakly coupled term..

Some of the known oscillation criteria are established by making use of a technique introduced by Kartsatos [5] where it is assumed that there exists a second derivative function

Abstract. Sets like P × R can be the limits of the blow ups of subgraphs of solutions of capillary surface or other prescribed mean curvature problems, for example. Danzhu Shi

It is natural to expect that if the solution of the limiting equation blows up in finite time, then so does the solution of the time-oscillating equation for |ω| large, but